In Descriptive Complexity, Immerman has
Corollary 7.23. The following conditions are equivalent:
1. P = NP.
2. Over finite, ordered structures, FO(LFP) = SO.
This can be thought of as "amplifying" P=NP to an equivalent statement over (presumably) larger complexity classes. Note that SO captures the polynomial-time hierarchy PH, and that FO(LFP) captures P, so this can be thought of as P=NP iff P=PH.
(The interesting part of this is the statement that P=NP implies P=PH; it is trivial that P=CC implies P=NP for any class CC that contains NP. Immerman simply remarks "if P=NP then PH=NP", presumably because P=NP can be used with the oracle definition of PH to show inductively that the whole hierarchy collapses.)
My question is:
How much further can P=NP be amplified in this way?
In particular, what is the largest known class CC' such that P=NP implies P=CC', and the smallest class CC such that P=NP implies CC=NP? This would allow P=NP to be replaced by the equivalent question CC=CC'. P appears to be a rather powerful class, which seems to provide little "wiggle room" for arguments trying to separate it from NP: how far can the wiggle room be amplified?
I would of course also be interested in an argument that shows that P=PH is the limit of this approach.
Edit: note the closely related question Why doesn't P=NP imply P=AP (i.e. P=PSPACE)? which focuses on the other direction, why we don't have proofs that P=PSPACE. Answers there by Kaveh and Peter Shor argue that the number of alternations being fixed is key. Another related question is A decision problem which is not known to be in PH but will be in P if P=NP which asks for a candidate problem; the answers there also can be used to construct answers for this question, although these classes are somewhat artificial (thanks to Tsuyoshi Ito for pointing this out). In a more general setting, Collapsing of exptime and alternation bounded turing machine asks whether a local collapse at any level in an alternation hierarchy induces an upward collapse, as happens with the polynomial-time hierarchy.
From Russell Impagliazzo's comment:
As a way of formalizing what languages are in $\mathsf{P}$ if $\mathsf{P}=\mathsf{NP}$, Regan introduced the complexity class $\mathsf{H}$. A language $L$ is in $\mathsf{H}$ if and only if $L$ is in $\mathsf{P}^O$ relative to every oracle $O$ so that $\mathsf{P}^O=\mathsf{NP}^O$. Thus, $L$ is in $\mathsf{H}$ if the statement $\mathsf{P}=\mathsf{NP} \implies L\in\mathsf{P}$ relativizes. $\mathsf{PH} \subseteq \mathsf{H} \subseteq \mathsf{AltTime}(O(\lg\lg n),\mathsf{poly})$. From Toda's theorem, and some of the lemmas in Toda's theorem, it is also true that $\mathsf{H} \subseteq \mathsf{P}^{\mathsf{mod}_q \mathsf{P}}$ for every $q$. Basically, any oracle satisfying $\mathsf{P}^O=\mathsf{NP}^O$ gives a new upper bound on $\mathsf{H}$. It is open whether $\mathsf{H}=\mathsf{PH}$.
And from Lance Fortnow's comment:
Let $f(n)$ be any unbounded function. $\mathsf{H}$ is not contained in $\mathsf{AltTime}(f(n),\mathsf{poly})$ and if you could prove $\mathsf{P}=\mathsf{NP}$ implies $\mathsf{P}=\mathsf{AltTime}(f(n),\mathsf{poly})$ then $\mathsf{NP}$ is different than $\mathsf{L}$.
For definition of $\mathsf{H}$ see definition 6.3 in
External links referenced by this document:
Local articles referenced by this article: